The Truth About Morality

Follow on

Though philosophers and religious authorities have debated the question of morality (i.e., what constitutes good and evil) for centuries, Buddhism offers a relatively straightforward answer: good, or right, is that which increases the joy or decreases the suffering of conscious creatures and therefore a priori should always be done, and evil, or wrong, that which does the opposite and therefore should not. Said another way, good is that which protects conscious creatures from harm, and evil that which subjects them to it. Good is also that which is just and fair, evil that which is unjust and unfair.

MORAL DILEMMAS

Interestingly, research has begun to show that belief in good and evil as conceptualized in Buddhism may be far more universal than previously thought. In an Internet study by psychologist Marc Hauser and colleagues, 5,000 subjects in 120 countries were presented three moral scenarios and one control scenario and asked both to render moral judgments and to justify them. One scenario, for example, described the following conundrum: Denise is riding a train when she hears the engineer suddenly shout that the brakes have failed. The driver then faints from the shock. On the track ahead stand five people who are unable to get off the track in time to avoid being hit by the train. Denise sees a sidetrack leading off to the right onto which she can steer the train, but one person stands on that track as well. She can turn the train, killing the one person, or do nothing and allow the five people to be killed instead. Was it morally permissible, Hauser and his colleagues wanted to know, for Denise to switch the train to the sidetrack?

Results showed that an astounding 89 percent of subjects agreed that Denise should steer the train onto the sidetrack; in fact, the subjects agreed about which actions were moral and which weren’t in most of the scenarios, delineating in the process a set of moral principles that seem to be shared by members of all cultures—namely, that it’s less morally permissible to intentionally harm someone than to allow them to be harmed, that it’s less morally permissible to invent a way to cause harm than to cause harm with an existing threat, and that it’s less morally permissible to cause harm directly than to cause it indirectly. Yet the vast majority of subjects couldn’t name these reasons as their underlying justification for judging the actions in each scenario as they did.

Which, in fact, other research suggests may be the norm. When we take moral action, we seem to rely not so much on moral reasoning as on moral intuition and then work backward to rationalize the judgments we’ve already made. (Which isn’t to say our moral intuition can’t and shouldn’t be influenced by reason, but rather that our moral intuition remains the primary driver of our moral decision making.) Where does our moral intuition come from? The answer isn’t yet clear. We know only that its rudiments seem to be present far earlier than we previously thought: research shows that children as young as three years old—an age at which it’s been demonstrated we have no ability to articulate or even understand the concepts of right, wrong, or justice—have a negative emotional reaction to being given fewer stickers than their peers when they make an equal contribution to cleaning up a roomful of toys.

All of which raises the intriguing possibility that the Buddhist conception of good as any action intended to prevent harm or provide help (that is, halt suffering or bring joy) may actually be rooted not in the authority of a god or a religion or a philosophy but in the psychological and perhaps even neurological processes of the human mind.

WHAT CONSTITUTES HARM?

Yet though we all seem to agree, according to Hauser’s study, that causing harm is wrong, in many cases we just as clearly disagree—often dramatically, violently, and tragically—about what harm is. In fact, the things people consider harmful vary not only from culture to culture, but also across one culture over time and from person to person within a culture. Consider, for example, how strongly people across the globe disagree about whether harm is caused by premarital sex. What’s more, even when people do agree about what constitutes harm, they often disagree about which harms are worse than others. We can see this in the strong disagreement about whether aborting a fetus on balance causes more harm than forcing a woman to carry an unwanted child to term.

How then are we to figure out what’s right and wrong when confronted with the kind of complex moral conundrums we encounter in the real world? A belief in moral relativism, meaning that right and wrong are determined by local culture and custom, would seem to ignore the fact that people can disagree about what defines harm without disagreeing that harm defines evil. And yet a belief in moral absolutism—that some particular actions are always right or always wrong in all situations and therefore that context is irrelevant—ignores the fact that often the choice we make to prevent one kind of harm also represents a choice to cause another. That is to say, our choices are rarely between right and wrong, but are almost always between wrong and less wrong (meaning harmful and less harmful). And unlike the definition of wrong itself, what’s wrong and less wrong does change depending on the context. Killing someone, for example, would be considered wrong according to the Buddhist definition, but killing someone may be “less wrong” if doing so is the only way to prevent the deaths of five others, or is done to end the life of a person suffering agonizing pain from a terminal disease.

Unfortunately, our ability to calculate all the various harms we both prevent and produce with any moral choice dwindles rapidly as we move away in both time and place from the situation in which we choose it. How can we ever know our action to prevent harm today won’t cause more harm tomorrow, or that our action to prevent harm here won’t produce harm there? The answer, of course, is that we can’t. In fact, given our propensity to make moral decisions based on intuition as well as our inability to foresee all the consequences of our decisions when we make them, we might argue that the only thing of which we should be certain (besides that we should always seek to minimize suffering and maximize joy) is that our best moral judgment will always be, to some degree, flawed.

A BALANCING ACT

We can perhaps be helped by logic, which tells us, among other things, that we should assign greater weight to proven harms (like stealing) than to unproven harms (like cursing God’s name). We could also argue that if we ever find ourselves convinced beyond any doubt that our action is absolutely right, good, and just, we should consider we’re probably looking at our choice and the context in which we make it too simplistically. If we’re not making our moral choices with some degree of difficulty and even regret, we’re probably not thinking about them carefully enough. Finally, we could say that if we find ourselves unable to identify a person or group who won’t in some way be harmed by our choice, or if we can but we don’t care about the harm our choice will inflict upon them–if we don’t genuinely lament having to pay the price of one harm to buy avoidance of another–we must indeed consider ourselves at risk for becoming a monster. What makes people monsters, in other words, isn’t their belief that the ends justify the means. The ends must always justify the means. What makes people monsters is that they don’t agonize over the means they feel forced to choose.

To those who might be tempted to cite our flawed judgment as a reason to avoid choosing at all, Buddhism would counter that not choosing is even worse than choosing something “less wrong.” For as Edmund Burke reminds us, all that’s necessary for the triumph of evil is for good men to do nothing. In fact, from a Buddhist perspective, allowing an injustice to occur when we have the power to prevent it is to become complicit in committing that injustice ourselves. Justice, in the Buddhist worldview, exists only because human beings make the effort to stand against injustice.

###

Note: This post was excerpted from my book, The Undefeated Mind. Readers interested in the references that support the ideas listed above are invited to refer to Chapter 5, “Stand Alone.”

 

Next Week: Time Anxiety

Leave A Comment

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

  • Nice thinking, Alex. I have referenced it on our blog today(RangerAgainstWar) as we have been delving into this area recently. Imagine—a war blog discussing morality; yet even that most unfortunate human endeavor must be just and abide by some measure of morality.

    Interesting are recent studies suggesting we “choose” for things a nanosecond before we actually make a move for them, suggesting we “know things in our bones” (?) Morality may be one of these things we know.

  • Very interesting. You point so well that one of the elements of making moral decisions is that we can rarely, given our human limitations, predict all the unintended consequences, whether good or bad, that will result from a particular choice. For example, in preparation for going to India I read a report of a village that had been given running water in their homes by a charitable NGO. On the surface that would seem a wonderful thing that would decrease suffering and increase joy. However, the unintended consequence was that the emotional wellbeing of the women was negatively impacted by the loss of the community they experienced by gathering water at a central place, so much so that the suicide rate increased. I think humility is a healthy start to moral decision making.

  • “…of a god or a religion or a philosophy but in the psychological and perhaps even neurological processes of the human mind.”

    Framing moral intuition as an either or function of “a god” instead of the God capital “G” weights the question unfairly, and imbues the neurological processes of the human mind with sui generis. Buddhism is as much a “world view” as any comma, quote religion, so to be fair its either of the God or nihilism.

    As Alan Watts would say by the way, that’s not the Christian god-as-boss man. It is the God of the wiggly way the waves recede on the shore, and the grain appears in wood the same each and every time we come upon them.

  • Thanks for sharing your excerpt and for prompting Jerry’s insightful posting. Luhhv the wiggly.

    As to concept of moral dilemma, if I consider it in the genius light of Alan Watts’ quote “Problems that remain persistently insoluble should always be suspected as questions asked in the wrong way,” sure seems to me moral dilemma dissolves wiggly rapidly.

    Giselle Massi
    http://www.gisellemassi.com

  • Yes, you’ve hit the nail on the head, Dr. Lickerman. We are constantly confronted with moral choices that force us to choose that which does the least harm, and we have no way of knowing the ultimate consequences of those choices. Perhaps, in choosing to kill one rather than five, we have killed the one who could cure cancer or devise a way to feed millions of malnourished humans, but we must choose that which does the least harm given our limited knowledge. This morning, I began writing about this very concept for my post that will appear in my blog next tuesday. Thanks for your insightful post.

  • Much wonderful food for thought here and thank you Giselle for the quote of Alan Watts:

    “Problems that remain persistently insoluble should always be suspected as questions asked in the wrong way.”

    Can we get specific for a moment?

    My dear friends, married 25 years, have reached a moral dilemma in that hubby has discovered he is gay and wishes to pursue that lifestyle to some extent. He wishes to do so privately, so as to not disrupt or cause trauma to his children.

    The most common choice in this situation is to separate, causing pain and suffering to all concerned. Even though it appears the male has “won,” it comes at a high cost and even he does not escape the pain of separation. In this situation, it seems to me that the children suffer the most initially, but one or the other of the spouses suffer the most in the long run.

    Another option is to have an “open marriage” wherein both spouses are free to pursue other love interests as long as they do not disturb or cause harm to the family. This scenario allows both to seek “joy” and minimizes the pain for both as the family home-base remains intact.

    Some wives choose to accept their spouse’s on-the-side affair, as long as it does not touch the family. Sometimes even continuing to have relations with their spouse. The man gets his cake and gets to eat it, too, by having his special lover and not loosing his family. The wife suffers the intimacy that is shared with another, but as long as the man remains an active member of the family, the wife still retains the emotional intimacy of the marriage and family unit.

    The man could also choose to accept his sexuality, but not act on it. The man sacrifices himself for the sake of the family, making this much like the train scenario: sacrificing one for the many.

    The unseen trauma in each scenario is the suffering of the man, himself, coping with his new reality and the responsibility of having to make the most just choice. Or, he could choose the option that is most enticing to him.

    Of course, it is his choice, alone, but in terms of which causes the most joy and the least harm, which choice is the best choice?